What is it to Represent the World?

How, if at All, do Zalabardo and Price Differ?

Authors

  • Bethany Smith University College London

DOI:

https://doi.org/10.30827/trif.32831

Keywords:

Neo-Pragmatism, No-Fault Disagreements, Causality, Scientific Objectivity, Representationalism

Abstract

Zalabardo (2023) and Price (2023) largely agree on what it is to represent the world, by rejecting representationalism and using pragmatist meaning grounds, but disagree regarding whether the truth or falsehood is absolute and objective. The key to representing the world is to understand that it is at base the procedure for ascribing truth or falsehood that comprises the meaning ground of a sentence. Zalabardo has this as an absolute, accept or reject, objective process, and employs a strict divide between sentences as representational or non-representational in function. Price accepts pragmatist meaning grounds as providing meaning, but argues for the possibility of ‘no fault disagreements’ rather than ‘an absolute standard of correctness’ [Price (2023), p. 50] and envisions a graduated sliding position in terms of representational or non-representational function, which I am more sympathetic to. For Price, ‘meaning depends on what are at base simply contingent dispositions to treat one thing as like another’ (ibid.). Building on Ramsey- Wittgenstein’s hypothetical, future-oriented direction of thought and language (e.g. properties/ concepts as ‘dispositions’) [1930; 1929], Price suggests that the Predictive Processing Framework [Clark (2013); Godfrey-Smith (2013)], is largely consistent with his neo-pragmatism, excluding Hohwy’s Cartesianism (2013). Disagreements remain from outside and within neo-pragmatism concerning subjectivism about probability; the cosmological versus psychological understanding of global ‘now’ or ‘becoming’; the determinability/ openness of the future; the metaphysical question of what probabilities are, versus why we psychologically model probabilities; and finally, whether memory or agency is implicated in causal asymmetry. Price and Zalabardo’s divergence creates a fruitful new platform to investigate various issues arising e.g. Are we continually misrepresenting the world; does Zalabardo’s absolute standard of correctness stand up to scrutiny? A persuasive case has been made for pragmatism and pragmatist meaning grounds, which posit that representing the world involves the idea that meaning is grounded in the procedure for accepting/not-accepting a sentence, rather than via representationalism and representationalist meaning grounds, however I favour Price’s recognition of no-fault disagreements.

Downloads

Download data is not yet available.

References

ALBERT, D.Z. (2000), Time and Chance; London, Harvard University Press. DOI: https://doi.org/10.4159/9780674020139

BERENSTAIN, N. (2016), ‘What a Structuralist Theory of Properties Could Not Be,’ in The Metaphysics of Relations, ed. D. Yates and A. Marmodoro, Oxford, Oxford University Press. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198735878.003.0010

BOLTZMANN, L. (1895), ‘On Certain Questions of the Theory of Gases’, in Nature, 51, pp. 413-415. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1038/051413b0

CLARK, A. (2013), ‘Whatever Next? Predictive Brains, Situated Agents, and the Future of Cognitive Science’; Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36(3), pp. 181-204. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X12000477

DAINTON, B. (2010), Time and Space; London, Routledge. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/UPO9781844654437

DREIER, J. (2004), ‘Meta‐Ethics and the Problem of Creeping Minimalism’; Philosophical Perspectives 18, pp. 23-44. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1520-8583.2004.00019.x

DUHEM, P. (1991), The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory; Translated by P. P. Wiener. Princeton, Princeton University Press.

EARMAN, J. (2006), ‘The ‘‘Past Hypothesis’’: Not even false’; Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 37, pp. 399-430. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsb.2006.03.002

FARR, M. (2018), ‘Causation and Time Reversal’; British Journal for Philosophy of Science, axx025.

FERNANDES, A. (2017), ‘A Deliberative Approach to Causation’; Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 95(3), pp. 686-708. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1111/phpr.12443

FORBES, G. (draft forthcoming; 2024), The Times They Are A-Changin’: A Defence of the Growing Block View of Time.

GODFREY-SMITH, P. (2013), ‘John Dewey’s Experience and Nature’; Topoi 33(1), pp. 285–291. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-013-9214-7

HEALEY, R. (2017a), ‘Quantum States as Objective Informational Bridges’; Foundations of Physics 47(2), pp. 161-173. doi:10.1007/s10701–015–9949–7. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-015-9949-7

––– (2017b), The Quantum Revolution in Philosophy; Oxford, Oxford University Press.

––– (2020), ‘Pragmatist Quantum Realism’; in Scientific Realism and the Quantum, Steven French and Juha Saatsi (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 123-146. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198814979.003.0007

HEMMO, M. and SHENKER, O. (2016), ‘The Arrow of Time’; in Dolev, Y. & Roubach, M. (eds.), Cosmological and Psychological Time; Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science, Volume 285, pp. 155-164. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-22590-6_9

HOHWY, J. (2013), The Predictive Mind; Oxford University Press. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199682737.001.0001

JACKSON, F. (1998), From Metaphysics to Ethics: A Defense of Conceptual Analysis; Oxford, Oxford University Press.

KÖLBEL, M. (2004), ‘Faultless Disagreement’; Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 104, pp. 53-73. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.0066-7373.2004.00081.x

LEWIS, D. (1970), ‘General Semantics’; Synthese 22, pp. 18-67. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00413598

––– (1973), ‘Causation’; Journal of Philosophy 70, pp. 556-567. DOI: https://doi.org/10.2307/2025310

––– (1974), ‘Radical Interpretation’; Synthese 23, pp. 331-344. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00484599

––– (1986), On the Plurality of Worlds; Oxford, Blackwell.

––– (2009), ‘Ramseyan Humility’; in Conceptual Analysis and Philosophical Naturalism, ed. D. Braddon-Mitchell and R. Nola; Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

LYCAN, W. G. (1988), ‘Dennett’s Instrumentalism’; Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11, pp. 518–519. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X0005874X

MACARTHUR, D. and PRICE, H. (2007), ‘Pragmatism, Quasi-realism and the Global Challenge’; in Cheryl Misak (ed.), The New Pragmatists; Oxford, Oxford University Press. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780199279975.003.0006

MACFARLANE, J. (2007), ‘Relativism and Disagreement’; Philosophical Studies 132, pp. 17–31. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-006-9049-9

POINCARÉ, H. (1952), Science and Hypothesis; translated by G. B. Halsted; New York, Dover Publications.

PRICE, H. (1988), Facts and the Function of Truth; Oxford, Blackwell.

––– (1996), Time’s Arrow and Archimedes’ Point; New York, Oxford University Press.

––– (2003), ‘Truth as Convenient Friction’; The Journal of Philosophy, 100(4), pp. 167–190. DOI: https://doi.org/10.5840/jphil200310048

––– (2009), ‘The Semantic Foundations of Metaphysics’; in Ian Ravenscroft (ed.), Minds, Worlds and Conditionals: Essays in Honour of Frank Jackson; Oxford, Oxford University Press.

––– (2011), Naturalism Without Mirrors; New York, Oxford University Press.

––– (2015), ‘From Quasirealism to Global Expressivism — and Back Again?’; in R. Johnson and M. Smith (eds.), Passions and Projections: Themes from the Philosophy of Simon Blackburn; Oxford, Oxford University Press.

––– (2022), ‘Global Expressivism and Alethic Pluralism’; Synthese 200. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03874-w

––– (2023), ‘Time for Pragmatism’; in Gert, J. (Ed.), Neopragmatism: Interventions in First-order Philosophy; Online Edition, Oxford, Oxford Academic.

––– (forthcoming), ‘Review of Zalabardo, Pragmatist Semantics’; Mind.

PRICE, H. and WESLAKE, B. (2009), ‘The Time-Asymmetry of Causation’; in Helen Beebee et al. (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Causation; Oxford, Oxford University Press, pp. 414-443. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199279739.003.0021

RAWLS, J. (1971), A Theory of Justice; Belknap Press. DOI: https://doi.org/10.4159/9780674042605

TIMPSON, C. (2008), ‘Quantum Bayesianism: A Study’; Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 39(3), pp. 579-609. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2008.03.006. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsb.2008.03.006

WHEELER, J. (1978), ‘The “Past” and the “Delayed-Choice” Double-Slit Experiment’; in A. R. Marlow (ed.), Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Theory; New York, Academic Press. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/B978-0-12-473250-6.50006-6

WITTGENSTEIN, L. (1930), ‘MS107’; as catalogued in von Wright 1993.

ZALABARDO, J. (2000), ‘Realism Detranscendentalized’; European Journal of Philosophy 8, pp. 63–88. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1111/1468-0378.00101

––– (2012), ‘Semantic Normativity and Naturalism’; in Continuum Companion to Philosophy of Language, ed. M. García-Carpintero and M. Kölbel; London, Continuum.

––– (2019), ‘Belief, Desire and the Prediction of Behaviour’; Philosophical Issues 29, pp. 295–310. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1111/phis.12155

––– (2023), Pragmatist Semantics: A Use-Based Approach to Linguistic Representation; Online edition, Oxford, Oxford Academic.

––– (forthcoming-a), ‘Humility and Metaphysics’; Analytic Philosophy.

––– (forthcoming-b), ‘What Is Linguistic Interpretation?’; in Neopragmatism, ed. J. Gert; Oxford, Oxford University Press.

Downloads

Published

2024-12-31

How to Cite

Smith, B. (2024). What is it to Represent the World? How, if at All, do Zalabardo and Price Differ?. Teorema. International Journal of Philosophy, 43(3), 161–175. https://doi.org/10.30827/trif.32831

Issue

Section

Book Symposium: Pragmatist Semantics, by J. L. Zalabardo